Why consciousness is important




















Rather, several representatives of this approach attacked the hard problem of the origin of elementary forms of sentience or perceptual experience e. How successful these attacks have been, should be discussed elsewhere.

From my point of view, the sensorimotor theory Hurley, ; Noe, has not convincingly responded to arguments raised by it critics e.

If we assume that simple robots do not have conscious experience, the fact that the proposed embodied and enacted mechanisms of perception can be modeled in robots already refutes the idea that these mechanisms can explain consciousness. The sensorimotor theory is, of course, only one of the embodiment-grounded attempts to explain the emergence of consciousness.

Nevertheless, they have not yet given any systematic account of the transition from the alleged simple sentience to human consciousness, which is the theme of the present paper. Part 2 above exposed the idea that human consciousness is a secure space where behavioral actions are virtually performed, and their consequences are virtually apprehended.

In general, this idea is not new but goes back to the British associationism of the eighteenth century Hesslow, About 40 years ago, Ingvar ; also Ingvar and Philipsson, practically formulated the concept of consciousness as anticipatory simulations; unfortunately, he justified his conclusions by brain imaging data which appear to be of questionable quality today, not surprising given the enormous progress of brain imaging techniques since then. The same idea of covert behavior underlies the concept of efference copy von Holst and Mittelstaedt, , as well as some control-theoretical models that regard themselves as alternatives to the efference copy theory e.

Particularly interesting from the present viewpoint are the data that virtual performance of actions includes anticipation of action results with simultaneous inhibition of the overt execution of these actions Hesslow, Behavior, originally realized in large feedforward loops including bodily periphery and the environment, can subsequently be reduced to the loops within the brain. Notwithstanding the clear similarity between my VR metaphor and all these old and recent views, there are substantial differences as well.

The present approach is, in contrast, based on the presumption of the control theory that behavior is control of input rather than control of output and cannot, therefore, be regarded as a set of commands sent to muscles. The very sense of a virtual behavior is obtaining its virtual consequences.

But notwithstanding these rather minor differences between all these approaches regarded above in a cavalry manner and the present one, there is a very big difference in the kind of explanation. The primary interest of simulation theorists is a how -explanations. They ask, how, i. My point, to the contrary, is a why -explanation: why virtual behavior is realized thus and not differently.

For example, without the phylogenetic roots in playing behavior, simulated activity could not possess its astonishing freedom to initiate any virtual action in any circumstances, to interrupt or terminate at any deliberate point and to re-start at any moment.

The components of communication and tool usage also have profound effects on the nature of human consciousness, as we shall see in the next session. Thus consciousness is regarded as the product of cognitive activity converted into a form of language to be shared with others.

Indeed, what else is specific for human in contrast to the animal consciousness if not the fact that it is based on social cooperation and language-mediated communication? Crudely, many socio-linguistic theories may be classified into pre-structuralist e. The first stress the process of internalization in which social interpersonal processes are transformed into internal cognitive intrapersonal processes.

Consciousness, from this point of view, is the pattern of social relations for example, a child-parent interaction transported into the head. The second class of theories contends that consciousness is based upon hidden cultural and linguistic stereotypes e. The third view insists on the virtually absolute relativity of the structure and content of conscious human behavior and in contrast to structuralism its historical and ideological interpenetration.

This view, however, leaves unclear wherefrom the structures or the rules of the game take their stability and causal power if they are not filled by the content of a language-independent world. Post-structuralists capitalized on this inconsequence and proposed a radical solution for the above problem: if consciousness does not have any meaningful content besides the rules and structures of the game, then, it does not have any rules and structures either Derrida, Thus even the notion of symbolic game became much too restrictive since it may imply that there is something the symbols stand for—but in fact, they stand for nothing.

For itself i. Not only, therefore, everything is merely a sequence of signs, but these signs do not signify anything: the classical opposition between the signifying and the signified de Saussure, is thus annulled. Hence, consciousness is not a game, as previous socio-linguistic theories regarded it, but rather a free play Derrida, whose rules may appear and disappear like clouds in a windy day.

From the early socio-linguistic point of view, consciousness is its own manifestation in systems of signs. From the later socio-linguistic point of view, consciousness is just these systems of signs and nothing more. One can say that these views evolved from the theories of socio-linguistic foundation of consciousness, peaking in the linguistic determinism in Wittgenstein and Whorf , to the theories of the unlimited freedom of consciousness in its historic and linguistic realization.

This freedom, from their and my point of view, largely roots in the freedom of the sign, which, in its development from index to symbol, abandoned its causal link to its reference. Importantly, the notion of language as a symbolic game is not limited by syntax. Rather, it is the very meaning of the words which is determined by their location within the network of tacit verbal rules.

Because many very influential linguistic theories originally accrued in philology and cultural anthropology, they may appear to concern only particular forms of consciousness expressed, e.

This is not true. They left their trace even in strongly biological approaches to cognition and consciousness e. From the present point of view, socio-linguistic theories correctly emphasize communication and play as important sources of human consciousness. However, all these views, traditional and contemporary, philosophically or biologically oriented, completely miss the instrumental nature of human behavior. Many of them talk about tools; e. But besides this, our consciousness is based on simply tools, which are not words, not theories, just tools.

Using them, we either attain our goal if we correctly grasp the objective relation between elements of the environment and their properties , or not if our conceptions are wrong. Thus the results of tool usage continuously test the validity of our symbolic games.

If their concepts of sticks and boxes were true, they reached the banana, but when they were false, they remained hungry. It is true that, e. But in addition, the building has to withstand gravity, wind and possibly earthquakes.

But it is also important to remember that our ancestors failed to reach bananas using a bundle of straw, simply because the bundle was not hard. The theory of common working space CWS: Baars, , is probably the most elaborated psychological theory of consciousness in the last 30 years. The theory regards the mind as a coordinated activity of numerous highly specialized cognitive modules Fodor, , whose work is largely automatic. When some of these specialists meet a processing task for which no preprogrammed solution is available, they build a CWS to make this task as well as all proposed solutions open for every other module.

This can be compared with a large audience in which many small groups work each with its own problem, but there is also a possibility to broadcast a problem for the whole audience. Consciousness is this broadcasting; there is a competition for access to it, because the space is only one, and the tasks are many. Therefore, the most interesting processes determining the content of our consciousness are not those which happen in consciousness but those which decide what specialized module s should get access to it.

The CWS theory not only provides an explanation for very many characteristic properties of consciousness, but it is also quite compatible with other interesting theories e. The metaphor of consciousness behind the CWS model is that of a theater Baars, The CWS can be regarded as an open scene accessible for all cognitive modules.

The similarity between the theater metaphor and the VR metaphor is obvious. Both presume a scenery, a show, thus pointing to one of the key components of the present hypothesis, i. Both theater and VR are spaces where things are played. But in this play, we should not play down the differences between the two metaphors.

A theater presumes many spectators, who rather passively observe the actors' activity, whereas a VR is concentrated around a single participant, who is actively engaged in this reality. Furthermore, arbitrariness is much stronger in the theater than in the VR. Millions of people admire opera theater in which they witness how personages express their emotions by continuous singing, which would appear strange and silly in real life.

Also interestingly, the theater metaphor does not warrant the uniqueness of consciousness. Many cities have several theaters, and some people can visit two or three on an evening. Nevertheless, the most established version of the CWS theory assumed that there exists only one common space for each brain and each body, Shanahan, Many concrete predictions of the CWS theory result from the assumption of the strong competition between modules striving for the access to the only possibility to broadcast.

Later on Baars suggested that there can be multiple CWSs working in parallel. Baars and Dennett devoted a lot of intriguing pages to the issue of how this unity can be created by the distributed brain.

Neuroscientists Singer, ; Treisman, ; Tallon-Baudry, regard this question as the main question of the neurophysiological underpinnings of consciousness. Thus we are surprised that we have only one state of consciousness at one time, despite millions of parallel functioning neuronal circuits in our brain. However, we are not surprised when a big animal e. We don't regard this unity as a miracle and don't postulate a specific mechanism of binding these cells into a single organism.

Complex behavior is realized in the form of muscular synergies Bernstein, ; Gelfand et al. These synergies are motor equivalents of the CWS. The unity of consciousness is the unity of behavior. This does not mean that the unity is unproblematic, but the analogy with motor control indicates the correct name for the problem.

With the development of a motor skill, the synergy becomes more and more local until it is limited to those muscles only, whose participation is indispensable. Of course, when we talk about muscles we also mean the whole nervous apparatus these muscles are connected with. Therefore, as far as the unity of the CWS is the unity of complex behavior, there is no contradiction between the CWS theory and the present one. Accordingly, the control of new, unskilled actions is frequently conscious.

The question is why the common working place of consciousness is common. From my point of view, it is not because a group of processing modules has decided, in a democratic or dictatorial way, that a given piece of information is interesting enough to make it accessible for the whole audience, but because complex behavior cannot be organized other than by coordinating all activity to a common pattern.

Likewise, we do not make two conscious decisions simultaneously not because the two must compete for one scene, but because, if we did make them simultaneously, how would we realize these decisions? The answer is: serially, one after the other. The model is presented that conceives of human consciousness as a product of a phylogenetic interaction of three particular forms of animal behavior: play, tool use, and communication.

When the three components meet in humans, they strengthen and mutually reinforce each other producing positive feedback loop. Therefore, although all three elements of human consciousness are present in many animal species not necessarily human predecessors , there is no other species that plays, communicates and uses tools as much as humans do. The suggested three-component structure permits to easily explain most typical features of human conscious awareness: its recursive character, seriality, objectivity, close relation to semantic and episodic memory, etc.

Other specific features of human consciousness e. Finally, a comparison of the current approach with other theories of consciousness embodiment theories, simulation theories, common working place reveals, notwithstanding some similarities, important differences from all of them. Again due to space limits, the complex relationships of this model of consciousness with the multiple draft theory, the re-entrance theory, and the classical dualistic approach must remain outside the present text.

The author confirms being the sole contributor of this work and approved it for publication. The author declares that the research was conducted in the absence of any commercial or financial relationships that could be construed as a potential conflict of interest. Fragments of the text were written with the support of the Deutsche Forschungsgemeinschaft DFG , other portions were supported by Alexander von Humboldt Stiftung.

Some ideas presented here emerged in discussions with J. Vanessa Singh commented an early version of the manuscript. I am particularly indebted to my students because the general view presented in this paper could only be developed within the interaction during teaching. Ackermann, H. Brain mechanisms of acoustic communication in humans and nonhuman primates: an evolutionary perspective. Brain Sci. Ambrose, S. Paleolithic technology and human evolution. Science , — Anokhin, P.

Dartau, J. Epp, and V. Oxford: Pergamon Press. Google Scholar. Arbib, M. Language evolution: neural homologies and neuroinformatics. Neural Netw. Neural expectations: a possible evolutionary path from manual skills to language. Atkinson, R. Solso Potomac, MD: Erlbaum , — The control of short-term memory. Augustinus, A. Bekenntnisse Confessiones , Transl.

Baars, B. A Cognitive Theory of Consciousnes. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. PubMed Abstract Google Scholar. In the Theater of Consciousness.

Metaphors of consciousness and attention in the brain. Trends Neurosci. Baars, W. Banks, and J. Bargh, J. The unbearable automaticity of being. Barr, R. The role of sensory preconditioning in memory retrieval by preverbal infants.

Bartlett, F. Bauby, J. Le Scaphandre et le Papillon, 1st Edn. Paris: Editions Robert Laffont. Beckermann, A. Berlin: de Gruyter. Bennett, M. Philosophical Foundations of Neuroscience. Oxford: Blackwell. Beran, M. Bernard, C. An Introduction to the Study of Experimental Medicine. Henry Schuman, Inc. Bernstein, N. The Coordination and Regulation of Movements. Oxford: Pergamon. Bickhard, M. Consciousness and reflective consciousness.

Inter- and en-activism: some thoughts and comparisons. New Ideas Psychol. Interactivism and genetic epistemology. Birbaumer, N. Brain—computer interface in paralysis. Kinder auf Zeitreise. Bern: Huber. Boesch, C. What makes us human Homo sapiens? The challenge of cognitive cross-species comparison. Brembs, B. Brentano, F. Deskriptive Psychologie. Hamburg: Meiner. Brodgen, W. Sensory preconditioning. Buchler, J. Philosophical Writings of Peirce. New York, NY: Dover. Buffon, G. S Barr London: Covent Garden , 62— Burghardt, G.

Carbonell, E. The first hominin in Europa. Nature , — Cartmill, E. Orangutans modify their gestural signaling according to their audience's comprehension. Chalmers, D.

Cheney, D. How Monkeys See the World. Chomsky, N. Language and the mind. Today 1, 48— Knowledge of language: its elements and origins. Clark, A. Corballis, M. Csibra, G. Acta Psychol. Damasio, A. San Diego, CA: Harcourt. Dennett, D. Consciousness Explained. Derrida, J. Course in General Linguistics. Dewey, J. The reflex arc concept in psychology. Donaldson, M. The evolution of functionally referential meaning in a structured world.

Edelman, D. Identifying hallmarks of consciousness in non-mammalian species. Edelman, G. A Universe of Consciousness. How Matter Becomes Imagination. Eibl-Eibesfeldt, I. Die Biologie des Menschlichen Verhaltens. Weyarn: Seehamer. Erdelyi, M. The unified theory of repression. Flack, J. Context modulates signal meaning in primate communication.

Fodor, J. The Modularity of Mind. Fotheringhame, D. Rugg Hove: Psychology Press , 47— Foucault, M. Les Mots et les Choses. Paris: Gallimard. Freud, S. The Interpretations of Dreams , Vol. London: Hoghart. Frey, S. Tool use, communicative gesture and cerebral asymmetries in the modern human brain. B , — Friston, K. Prediction, perception and agency. Gabbert, F. Memory conformity: can eyewitnesses influence each other's memories for an event?

Galilei, G. Gelfand, I. Gibson, K. The evolution of lateral asymmetries, language, tool-use, and intellect.

Gregory, R. Marcel and E. Bisiach Oxford: Clarendon Press , — Eye and Brain: The Psychology of Seeing. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Grossberg, S. Studies in Mind and Brain, Vol. Dordrecht: Reidel Publishing Company. Grusz, R. The emulation theory of representation: motor control, imagery, and perception. Hacker, P. Language rules and pseudo-rules. Chomsky's problems. CrossRef Full Text. Hardcastle, V. Visual perception is not visual awareness. Heidegger, M.

Sein und Zeit. Herrmann, E. Apes' use of iconic cues in the object-choice task. Hershberger, W. Amsterdam: Elsevier , 3— Hesslow, G. Conscious thought as simulation of behavior and perception.

Trends Cogn. The cirrent status of the simulation theory of cognition. Brain Res. Hickman, L. The Essential Dewey Vol. Bloomington: Indiana University Press. Hobson, J. The Dreaming Brain. The cognitive neuroscience of sleep: neuronal systems, consciousness and learning. Hommel, B. Huber, L.

Technical intelligence in animals: the kea model. Huizinga, J. Humphrey, N. Seeing Red: A Study of Consciousness. Hunt, G. The right tool for the job: what strategies do wild New Caledonian crows use?

Hurley, S. In any development programme, raising consciousness is the starting point. In order for the work to be truly effective, each part of our philosophy must be brought to bear on the process.

Yet the process must begin somewhere, and starting with consciousness means the work has the greatest chance of success. The opening lines of A. It is, as far as he knows, the only way of coming downstairs, but sometimes he feels that there really is another way, if only he could stop bumping for a moment and think of it. Raising consciousness is about that moment of pause: stopping to think, to observe, to notice. Improving awareness, raising consciousness… you might wonder what that really means.

There are three critical elements that we explore with leaders when doing this work: values, personality, and emotions. For individuals to move forward, on their own or in a team, a strong understanding of these things is key. A higher state of consciousness helps you to take stock of what is already there. Baumeister, R. The self. In The handbook of social psychology 4th ed. Broughton, R. Homicidal somnambulism: A case report. DeWall, C. Evidence that logical reasoning depends on conscious processing.

Consciousness and Cognition, 17 3 , Koch, C. The quest for consciousness: A neurobiological approach. How does consciousness happen? Scientific American, 76— Martin, L. Can sleepwalking be a murder defense? Petty, R. Dual-process theories in social psychology. Shanks, D. Implicit learning.

Lamberts Ed.



0コメント

  • 1000 / 1000